This is a picture of Maurice Druon, the Honorary Perpetual Secretary of  L'Academie Francaise, the French Academy. He is splendidly attired in his  $68,000 uniform, befitting the role of the French Academy as legislating the  correct usage in French and perpetuating the language. The French Academy  has two main tasks: it compiles a dictionary of official French. They're now  working on their ninth edition, which they began in 1930, and they've reached  the letter P. They also legislate on correct usage, such as the proper term for  what the French call "email," which ought to be "courriel." The World Wide Web,  the French are told, ought to be referred to as "la toile d'araignee mondiale" --  the Global Spider Web -- recommendations that the French gaily ignore. Now,  this is one model of how language comes to be: namely, it's legislated by an  academy. But anyone who looks at language realizes that this is a rather silly  conceit, that language, rather, emerges from human minds interacting from one  another. And this is visible in the unstoppable change in language -- the fact that by the time the Academy finishes their dictionary, it will already be well out of  date. We see it in the constant appearance of slang and jargon, of the historical  change in languages, in divergence of dialects and the formation of new  languages. So language is not so much a creator or shaper of human nature,  so much as a window onto human nature. In a book that I'm currently working  on, I hope to use language to shed light on a number of aspects of human  nature, including the cognitive machinery with which humans conceptualize the  world and the relationship types that govern human interaction. And I'm going to  say a few words about each one this morning. Let me start off with a technical  problem in language that I've worried about for quite some time -- and indulge  me in my passion for verbs and how they're used. The problem is, which verbs  go in which constructions? The verb is the chassis of the sentence. It's the  framework onto which the other parts are bolted. Let me give you a quick  reminder of something that you've long forgotten. An intransitive verb, such as  "dine," for example, can't take a direct object. You have to say, "Sam dined," not, "Sam dined the pizza." A transitive verb mandates that there has to be an object  there: "Sam devoured the pizza." You can't just say, "Sam devoured." There are  dozens or scores of verbs of this type, each of which shapes its sentence. So, a  problem in explaining how children learn language, a problem in teaching  language to adults so that they don't make grammatical errors, and a problem in programming computers to use language is which verbs go in which  constructions. For example, the dative construction in English. You can say,  "Give a muffin to a mouse," the prepositional dative. Or, "Give a mouse a  muffin," the double-object dative. "Promise anything to her," "Promise her  anything," and so on. Hundreds of verbs can go both ways. So a tempting  generalization for a child, for an adult, for a computer is that any verb that can  appear in the construction, "subject-verb-thing-to-a-recipient" can also be  expressed as "subject-verb-recipient-thing." A handy thing to have, 

because language is infinite, and you can't just parrot back the sentences that  you've heard. You've got to extract generalizations so you can produce and  understand new sentences. This would be an example of how to do that.  Unfortunately, there appear to be idiosyncratic exceptions. You can say, "Biff  drove the car to Chicago," but not, "Biff drove Chicago the car." You can say,  "Sal gave Jason a headache," but it's a bit odd to say, "Sal gave a headache to  Jason." The solution is that these constructions, despite initial appearance, are  not synonymous, that when you crank up the microscope on human cognition,  you see that there's a subtle difference in meaning between them. So, "give the  X to the Y," that construction corresponds to the thought "cause X to go to Y."  Whereas "give the Y the X" corresponds to the thought "cause Y to have X."  Now, many events can be subject to either construal, kind of like the classic  figure-ground reversal illusions, in which you can either pay attention to the  particular object, in which case the space around it recedes from attention,  or you can see the faces in the empty space, in which case the object recedes  out of consciousness. How are these construals reflected in language? Well, in  both cases, the thing that is construed as being affected is expressed as the  direct object, the noun after the verb. So, when you think of the event as causing the muffin to go somewhere -- where you're doing something to the muffin -- you say, "Give the muffin to the mouse." When you construe it as "cause the mouse  to have something," you're doing something to the mouse, and therefore you  express it as, "Give the mouse the muffin." So which verbs go in which  construction -- the problem with which I began -- depends on whether the verb  specifies a kind of motion or a kind of possession change. To give something  involves both causing something to go and causing someone to have. To drive  the car only causes something to go, because Chicago's not the kind of thing  that can possess something. Only humans can possess things. And to give  someone a headache causes them to have the headache, but it's not as if  you're taking the headache out of your head and causing it to go to the other  person, and implanting it in them. You may just be loud or obnoxious, or some  other way causing them to have the headache. So, that's an example of the kind of thing that I do in my day job. So why should anyone care? Well, there are a  number of interesting conclusions, I think, from this and many similar kinds of  analyses of hundreds of English verbs. First, there's a level of fine-grained  conceptual structure, which we automatically and unconsciously compute  every time we produce or utter a sentence, that governs our use of language.  You can think of this as the language of thought, or "mentalese." It seems to be  based on a fixed set of concepts, which govern dozens of constructions and  thousands of verbs -- not only in English, but in all other languages –  fundamental concepts such as space, time, causation and human intention,  such as, what is the means and what is the ends? These are reminiscent of the  kinds of categories that Immanuel Kant argued are the basic framework for 

human thought, and it's interesting that our unconscious use of language seems to reflect these Kantian categories. Doesn't care about perceptual qualities, such as color, texture, weight and speed, which virtually never differentiate the use of  verbs in different constructions. An additional twist is that all of the constructions  

in English are used not only literally, but in a quasi-metaphorical way. For  example, this construction, the dative, is used not only to transfer things, but  also for the metaphorical transfer of ideas, as when we say, "She told a story to  me" or "told me a story," "Max taught Spanish to the students" or "taught the  students Spanish." It's exactly the same construction, but no muffins, no mice,  nothing moving at all. It evokes the container metaphor of communication, in  which we conceive of ideas as objects, sentences as containers, and  communication as a kind of sending. As when we say we "gather" our ideas, to  "put" them "into" words, and if our words aren't "empty" or "hollow," we might get these ideas "across" to a listener, who can "unpack" our words to "extract" their  "content." And indeed, this kind of verbiage is not the exception, but the rule. It's  very hard to find any example of abstract language that is not based on some  concrete metaphor. For example, you can use the verb "go" and the prepositions "to" and "from" in a literal, spatial sense. "The messenger went from Paris to  Istanbul." You can also say, "Biff went from sick to well." He needn't go  anywhere. He could have been in bed the whole time, but it's as if his health is a point in state space that you conceptualize as moving. Or, "The meeting went  from three to four," in which we conceive of time as stretched along a line.  Likewise, we use "force" to indicate not only physical force, as in, "Rose forced  the door to open," but also interpersonal force, as in, "Rose forced Sadie to go,"  not necessarily by manhandling her, but by issuing a threat. Or, "Rose forced  herself to go," as if there were two entities inside Rose's head, engaged in a tug  of a war. Second conclusion is that the ability to conceive of a given event in two different ways, such as "cause something to go to someone" and "causing  someone to have something," I think is a fundamental feature of human thought, and it's the basis for much human argumentation, in which people don't differ so  much on the facts as on how they ought to be construed. Just to give you a few  examples: "ending a pregnancy" versus "killing a fetus;" "a ball of cells" versus  "an unborn child;" "invading Iraq" versus "liberating Iraq;" "redistributing wealth"  versus "confiscating earnings." And I think the biggest picture of all would take  seriously the fact that so much of our verbiage about abstract events is based  on a concrete metaphor and see human intelligence itself as consisting of a  repertoire of concepts -- such as objects, space, time, causation and intention --  which are useful in a social, knowledge-intensive species, whose evolution you  can well imagine, and a process of metaphorical abstraction that allows us to  bleach these concepts of their original conceptual content -- space, time and  force -- and apply them to new abstract domains, therefore allowing a species  that evolved to deal with rocks and tools and animals, to conceptualize 

mathematics, physics, law and other abstract domains. Well, I said I'd talk about two windows on human nature -- the cognitive machinery with which we  conceptualize the world, and now I'm going to say a few words about the  relationship types that govern human social interaction, again, as reflected in  language. And I'll start out with a puzzle, the puzzle of indirect speech acts.  Now, I'm sure most of you have seen the movie "Fargo." And you might  remember the scene in which the kidnapper is pulled over by a police officer,  is asked to show his driver's license and holds his wallet out with a 50-dollar bill  extending at a slight angle out of the wallet. And he says, "I was just thinking  that maybe we could take care of it here in Fargo," which everyone, including  the audience, interprets as a veiled bribe. This kind of indirect speech is rampant in language. For example, in polite requests, if someone says, "If you could pass the guacamole, that would be awesome," we know exactly what he means,  even though that's a rather bizarre concept being expressed. "Would you like to  come up and see my etchings?" I think most people understand the intent  behind that. And likewise, if someone says, "Nice store you've got there. It would be a real shame if something happened to it" -- we understand that as a veiled  threat, rather than a musing of hypothetical possibilities. So the puzzle is, why  are bribes, polite requests, solicitations and threats so often veiled? No one's  fooled. Both parties know exactly what the speaker means, and the speaker  knows the listener knows that the speaker knows that the listener knows, etc.,  etc. So what's going on? I think the key idea is that language is a way of  negotiating relationships, and human relationships fall into a number of types.  There's an influential taxonomy by the anthropologist Alan Fiske, in which  relationships can be categorized, more or less, into communality, which works  on the principle "what's mine is thine, what's thine is mine," the kind of mindset  that operates within a family, for example; dominance, whose principle is "don't  mess with me;" reciprocity, "you scratch my back, I'll scratch yours;" and  sexuality, in the immortal words of Cole Porter, "Let's do it." Now, relationship  types can be negotiated. Even though there are default situations in which one  of these mindsets can be applied, they can be stretched and extended. For  example, communality applies most naturally within family or friends, but it can  be used to try to transfer the mentality of sharing to groups that ordinarily would  not be disposed to exercise it. For example, in brotherhoods, fraternal  organizations, sororities, locutions like "the family of man," you try to get people  who are not related to use the relationship type that would ordinarily be  appropriate to close kin. Now, mismatches -- when one person assumes one  relationship type, and another assumes a different one -- can be awkward. If you went over and you helped yourself to a shrimp off your boss' plate, for example,  that would be an awkward situation. Or if a dinner guest after the meal pulled  out his wallet and offered to pay you for the meal, that would be rather awkward  as well. In less blatant cases, there's still a kind of negotiation that often goes 

on. In the workplace, for example, there's often a tension over whether an  employee can socialize with the boss, or refer to him or her on a first-name  basis. If two friends have a reciprocal transaction, like selling a car, it's well  known that this can be a source of tension or awkwardness. In dating, the  transition from friendship to sex can lead to, notoriously, various forms of  awkwardness, and as can sex in the workplace, in which we call the conflict  between a dominant and a sexual relationship "sexual harassment." Well, what  does this have to do with language? Well, language, as a social interaction, has  to satisfy two conditions. You have to convey the actual content -- here we get  back to the container metaphor. You want to express the bribe, the command,  the promise, the solicitation and so on, but you also have to negotiate and  maintain the kind of relationship you have with the other person. The solution, I  think, is that we use language at two levels: the literal form signals the safest  relationship with the listener, whereas the implicated content -- the reading  between the lines that we count on the listener to perform -- allows the listener  to derive the interpretation which is most relevant in context, which possibly  initiates a changed relationship. The simplest example of this is in the polite  request. If you express your request as a conditional -- "if you could open the  window, that would be great" -- even though the content is an imperative, the  fact that you're not using the imperative voice means that you're not acting as if  you're in a relationship of dominance, where you could presuppose the  compliance of the other person. On the other hand, you want the damn  guacamole. By expressing it as an if-then statement, you can get the message  across without appearing to boss another person around. And in a more subtle  way, I think, this works for all of the veiled speech acts involving plausible  deniability: the bribes, threats, propositions, solicitations and so on. One way of  thinking about it is to imagine what it would be like if language -- where it could  only be used literally. And you can think of it in terms of a game-theoretic payoff  matrix. Put yourself in the position of the kidnapper wanting to bribe the officer.  There's a high stakes in the two possibilities of having a dishonest officer or an  honest officer. If you don't bribe the officer, then you will get a traffic ticket -- or,  as is the case of "Fargo," worse -- whether the honest officer is honest or  dishonest. Nothing ventured, nothing gained. In that case, the consequences  are rather severe. On the other hand, if you extend the bribe, if the officer is  dishonest, you get a huge payoff of going free. If the officer is honest, you get a  huge penalty of being arrested for bribery. So this is a rather fraught situation.  On the other hand, with indirect language, if you issue a veiled bribe, then the  dishonest officer could interpret it as a bribe, in which case you get the payoff of  going free. The honest officer can't hold you to it as being a bribe, and therefore, you get the nuisance of the traffic ticket. So you get the best of both worlds. And  a similar analysis, I think, can apply to the potential awkwardness of a sexual  solicitation, and other cases where plausible deniability is an asset. I think this 

affirms something that's long been known by diplomats -- namely, that the  vagueness of language, far from being a bug or an imperfection, actually might  be a feature of language, one that we use to our advantage in social  interactions. So to sum up: language is a collective human creation, reflecting  human nature, how we conceptualize reality, how we relate to one another. And  then by analyzing the various quirks and complexities of language, I think we  can get a window onto what makes us tick. Thank you very much. 



آخر تعديل: الثلاثاء، 15 أبريل 2025، 7:32 ص